Publiuslogic Links
|
A Theory of
Knowledge I INTRODUCTION
Plato (circa 428-c. 347 BC), Greek philosopher, one of the
most creative and influential thinkers in Western philosophy. II LIFE As a young man
Plato had political ambitions, but he became disillusioned by the political
leadership in Athens. He eventually became a disciple of Socrates, accepting
his basic philosophy and dialectical style of debate: the pursuit of truth
through questions, answers, and additional questions. Plato witnessed the
death of Socrates at the hands of the Athenian democracy in 399 BC. Perhaps
fearing for his own safety, he left Athens temporarily and traveled to Italy,
Sicily, and Egypt. In 387 Plato
founded the Academy in Athens, the institution often described as the first
European university. It provided a comprehensive curriculum, including such
subjects as astronomy, biology, mathematics, political theory, and
philosophy. Aristotle was the Academy's most prominent student. Pursuing an
opportunity to combine philosophy and practical politics, Plato went to
Sicily in 367 to tutor the new ruler of Syracuse, Dionysius the Younger, in
the art of philosophical rule. The experiment failed. Plato made another trip
to Syracuse in 361, but again his engagement in Sicilian affairs met with
little success. The concluding years of his life were spent lecturing at the
Academy and writing. He died at about the age of 80 in Athens in 348 or 347
BC. III WORKS A Early Dialogues The dialogues
may be divided into early, middle, and later periods of composition. The
earliest represent Plato's attempt to communicate the philosophy and
dialectical style of Socrates. Several of these dialogues take the same form.
Socrates, encountering someone who claims to know much, professes to be
ignorant and seeks assistance from the one who knows. As Socrates begins to
raise questions, however, it becomes clear that the one reputed to be wise really
does not know what he claims to know, and Socrates emerges as the wiser one
because he at least knows that he does not know. Such knowledge, of course,
is the beginning of wisdom. Included in this group of dialogues are Charmides (an attempt to define temperance),
Lysis (a discussion of friendship),
Laches (a pursuit of the meaning of
courage), Protagoras (a defense of
the thesis that virtue is knowledge and can be taught), Euthyphro (a consideration of the nature of piety), and Book I of
the Republic (a discussion of
justice). B Middle and Late Dialogues The dialogues
of the middle and later periods of Plato's life reflect his own philosophical
development. The ideas in these works are attributed by most scholars to Plato
himself, although Socrates continues to be the main character in many of the
dialogues. The writings of the middle period include Gorgias (a consideration of several ethical questions), Meno (a discussion of the nature of
knowledge), the Apology (Socrates'
defense of himself at his trial against the charges of atheism and corrupting
Athenian youth), Crito (Socrates'
defense of obedience to the laws of the state), Phaedo (the death scene of Socrates, in which he discusses the
theory of Forms, the nature of the soul, and the question of immortality),
the Symposium (Plato's outstanding
dramatic achievement, which contains several speeches on beauty and love),
the Republic (Plato's supreme
philosophical achievement, which is a detailed discussion of the nature of
justice). The works of
the later period include the Theaetetus
(a denial that knowledge is to be identified with sense perception), Parmenides (a critical evaluation of
the theory of Forms), Sophist (further
consideration of the theory of Ideas, or Forms), Philebus (a discussion of the relationship between pleasure and
the good), Timaeus (Plato's views
on natural science and cosmology), and the Laws (a more practical analysis of political and social issues). IV THEORY OF FORMS
A Theory of Knowledge Plato's theory of Forms and his
theory of knowledge are so interrelated that they must be discussed together.
Influenced by Socrates, Plato was convinced that knowledge is attainable. He
was also convinced of two essential characteristics of knowledge. First,
knowledge must be certain and infallible. Second, knowledge must have as its
object that which is genuinely real as contrasted with that which is an
appearance only. Because that which is fully real must, for Plato, be fixed,
permanent, and unchanging, he identified the real with the ideal realm of
being as opposed to the physical world of becoming. One consequence of this
view was Plato's rejection of empiricism, the claim that knowledge is derived
from sense experience. He thought that propositions derived from sense
experience have, at most, a degree of probability. They are not certain.
Furthermore, the objects of sense experience are changeable phenomena of the
physical world. Hence, objects of sense experience are not proper objects of
knowledge. Plato's own
theory of knowledge is found in the Republic,
particularly in his discussion of the image of the divided line and the myth
of the cave. In the former, Plato distinguishes between two levels of
awareness: opinion and knowledge. Claims or assertions about the physical or
visible world, including both commonsense observations and the propositions
of science, are opinions only. Some of these opinions are well founded; some
are not; but none of them counts as genuine knowledge. The higher level of
awareness is knowledge, because there reason, rather than sense experience,
is involved. Reason, properly used, results in intellectual insights that are
certain, and the objects of these rational insights are the abiding
universals, the eternal Forms or substances that constitute the real world. The myth of
the cave describes individuals chained deep within the recesses of a cave.
Bound so that vision is restricted, they cannot see one another. The only
thing visible is the wall of the cave upon which appear shadows cast by
models or statues of animals and objects that are passed before a brightly
burning fire. Breaking free, one of the individuals escapes from the cave
into the light of day. With the aid of the sun, that person sees for the
first time the real world and returns to the cave with the message that the
only things they have seen heretofore are shadows and appearances and that
the real world awaits them if they are willing to struggle free of their
bonds. The shadowy environment of the cave symbolizes for Plato the physical
world of appearances. Escape into the sun-filled setting outside the cave
symbolizes the transition to the real world, the world of full and perfect
being, the world of Forms, which is the proper object of knowledge. B Nature of Forms The theory of
Forms may best be understood in terms of mathematical entities. A circle, for
instance, is defined as a plane figure composed of a series of points, all of
which are equidistant from a given point. No one has ever actually seen such
a figure, however. What people
have actually seen are drawn figures that are more or less close
approximations of the ideal circle. In fact, when mathematicians define a
circle, the points referred to are not spatial points at all; they are
logical points. They do not occupy space. Nevertheless, although the Form of
a circle has never been seen—indeed, could never be seen—mathematicians and
others do in fact know what a circle is. That they can define a circle is
evidence that they know what it is. For Plato, therefore, the Form
“circularity” exists, but not in the physical world of space and time. It
exists as a changeless object in the world of Forms or Ideas, which can be
known only by reason. Forms have greater reality than objects in the physical
world both because of their perfection and stability and because they are
models, resemblance to which gives ordinary physical objects whatever reality
they have. Circularity, squareness, and triangularity are excellent examples,
then, of what Plato meant by Forms. An object existing in the physical world
may be called a circle or a square or a triangle only to the extent that it
resembles (“participates in” is Plato's phrase) the Form “circularity” or
“squareness” or “triangularity.” Plato extended
his theory beyond the realm of mathematics. Indeed, he was most interested in
its application in the field of social ethics. The theory was his way of
explaining how the same universal term can refer to so many particular things
or events. The word justice, for
example, can be applied to hundreds of particular acts because these acts
have something in common, namely, their resemblance to, or participation in,
the Form “justice.” An individual is human to the extent that he or she
resembles or participates in the Form “humanness.” If “humanness” is defined
in terms of being a rational animal, then an individual is human to the
extent that he or she is rational. A particular act is courageous or cowardly
to the extent that it participates in its Form. An object is beautiful to the
extent that it participates in the Idea, or Form, of beauty. Everything in
the world of space and time is what it is by virtue of its resemblance to, or
participation in, its universal Form. The ability to define the universal
term is evidence that one has grasped the Form to which that universal
refers. Plato
conceived the Forms as arranged hierarchically; the supreme Form is the Form
of the Good, which, like the sun in the myth of the cave, illuminates all the
other Ideas. There is a sense in which the Form of the Good represents
Plato's movement in the direction of an ultimate principle of explanation.
Ultimately, the theory of Forms is intended to explain how one comes to know
and also how things have come to be as they are. In philosophical language,
Plato's theory of Forms is both an epistemological (theory of knowledge) and
an ontological (theory of being) thesis. V POLITICAL THEORY
The Republic, Plato's major political
work, is concerned with the question of justice and therefore with the
questions “what is a just state” and “who is a just individual?” The ideal
state, according to Plato, is composed of three classes. The economic
structure of the state is maintained by the merchant class. Security needs
are met by the military class, and political leadership is provided by the
philosopher-kings. A particular person's class is determined by an
educational process that begins at birth and proceeds until that person has
reached the maximum level of education compatible with interest and ability.
Those who complete the entire educational process become philosopher-kings.
They are the ones whose minds have been so developed that they are able to
grasp the Forms and, therefore, to make the wisest decisions. Indeed, Plato's
ideal educational system is primarily structured so as to produce
philosopher-kings. Plato
associates the traditional Greek virtues with the class structure of the
ideal state. Temperance is the unique virtue of the artisan class; courage is
the virtue peculiar to the military class; and wisdom characterizes the
rulers. Justice, the fourth virtue, characterizes society as a whole. The
just state is one in which each class performs its own function well without
infringing on the activities of the other classes. Plato divides
the human soul into three parts: the rational part, the will, and the
appetites. The just person is the one in whom the rational element, supported
by the will, controls the appetites. An obvious analogy exists here with the
threefold class structure of the state, in which the enlightened
philosopher-kings, supported by the soldiers, govern the rest of society. VI ETHICS Plato's ethical theory rests on
the assumption that virtue is knowledge and can be taught, which has to be
understood in terms of his theory of Forms. As indicated previously, the
ultimate Form for Plato is the Form of the Good, and knowledge of this Form
is the source of guidance in moral decision making. Plato also argued that to
know the good is to do the good. The corollary of this is that anyone who
behaves immorally does so out of ignorance. This conclusion follows from
Plato's conviction that the moral person is the truly happy person, and
because individuals always desire their own happiness, they always desire to
do that which is moral. VII ART Plato had an
essentially antagonistic view of art and the artist, although he approved of certain
religious and moralistic kinds of art. Again, his approach is related to his
theory of Forms. A beautiful flower, for example, is a copy or imitation of
the universal Forms “flowerness” and “beauty.” The physical flower is one
step removed from reality, that is, the Forms. A picture of the flower is,
therefore, two steps removed from reality. This also meant that the artist is
two steps removed from knowledge, and, indeed, Plato's frequent criticism of
the artists is that they lack genuine knowledge of what they are doing.
Artistic creation, Plato observed, seems to be rooted in a kind of inspired
madness. VIII INFLUENCE Plato's influence throughout the
history of philosophy has been monumental. When he died, Speusippus became
head of the Academy. The school continued in existence until AD 529, when it
was closed by the Byzantine emperor Justinian I, who objected to its pagan
teachings. Plato's impact on Jewish thought is apparent in the work of the
1st-century Alexandrian philosopher Philo Judaeus. Neoplatonism, founded by
the 3rd-century philosopher Plotinus, was an important later development of
Platonism. The theologians Clement of Alexandria, Origen, and St. Augustine
were early Christian exponents of a Platonic perspective. Platonic ideas have
had a crucial role in the development of Christian theology and also in
medieval Islamic thought (see
Islam). During the
Renaissance, the primary focus of Platonic influence was the Florentine
Academy, founded in the 15th century near Florence. Under the leadership of
Marsilio Ficino, members of the Academy studied Plato in the original Greek.
In England, Platonism was revived in the 17th century by Ralph Cudworth and
others who became known as the Cambridge Platonists. Plato's influence has
been extended into the 20th century by such thinkers as Alfred North
Whitehead, who once paid him tribute by describing the history of philosophy
as simply “a series of footnotes to Plato.” See also Greek Philosophy; Idealism; Metaphysics; Philosophy. Contributed By: Publiuslogic Links, Return to What is Ra? |
Ancient Egyptian
History
Measurements & Conversion Tables Pyramid & Pyramid Math with Polyhedron Back To Zero Mathematics
Deep Secrets
Measurements of Cubits |